Friday, December 16, 2011

Christopher Hitchens In Memoriam

The death yesterday of Christopher Hitchens is indeed, as he himself noted in the remarkable Jeremy Paxman interview a year ago, a terrible waste. And so is, as he himself again added, the premature death of any individual who still has a lot to offer to his friends or maybe the world at large as well. The way he faced death has been remarkable. He was calm and humble before it, but in a supremely heroic way, not deigning to give an inch with respect to his atheism. I believe that this is a lasting and valuable legacy, whatever one may have to say about the substance of his various convictions and stances. There was an exemplary quality about him as a human being, especially towards the end. He may have declared in that interview that he does not particularly fancy the word "mellow". But I do think that he had mellowed indeed, primarily in relation to himself, without of course repudiating any of his polemical positions or his doggedly adversarial method.

Hitchens was immensely talented in the oratorical arts and his various turns of phrase on diverse matters are legendary (and mostly apt). A flood of words came out of him, most of the time in a brilliant, albeit somewhat overloaded, order. He had mastered perfectly the technique of eristics, out some kind of instinct it seems to me, although this did not preclude his attachment to principle. As a controversialist he dazzled, although it has to be said that he did it in the cocksure way that is the stamp of Oxford and which can be very annoying sometimes. For the problem with Hitchens was that he was absolutely convinced that he was right in all the positions that he took over the years -despite the fact that those of recent vintage simply butt heads with many of the earlier ones.

He was fundamentally misguided in his support of the invasion of Iraq. This was a miserable failure of judgment which he did not at all hedge or revise until the end. It constitutes a blemish that will now unfortunately never be erased. He subsequent friendship with unsavory neo-con characters such as Wolfowitz signified a further corruption of his moral mettle, upon which he himself placed so much value. His notion that the appalling civilian casualties subsequent to the invasion -casualties due to the arrogant sloppiness of that imperialist venture- do not go on the account of Bush and Co. is simply ludicrous. And so is his denial that the emergence and widening influence of Al Qaida in Iraq is again a result of American military and political brutishness-cum-incompetence in the matter. If one adds the mockery of international legality by the Bushies (do you remember Colin Powell lying through his teeth before the security council in February, 2003?), as well as the immense increase in the Iranian Ayatollahs' influence over Iraqi affairs, one can gage the blindness of the Hitchens position. Bush's murderous Iraq sideshow did immense damage to America and its people, a country that Hitchens rightly loved and defended with such vehemence.

In the matter of God, now, we will never know to what extent his mother's tragic end in Athens, as well as his dabbling in Greek Orthodoxy after his marriage to his Greek first wife is causally connected to the subsequent ferocity of his atheism. I suspect that it is, but I cannot prove it because it requires factual as well as psychoanalytic validation.

Let me summarize my opinion of his views in this department: firstly, he was absolutely right in his scathing demolition of the claims of churches, divines etc. to be custodians of the "word of God" and in his denunciation of the evil consequences that have historically flowed from these ecclesiastical conspiracies; secondly, he was absolutely wrong in thinking that these undeniable facts have any bearing whatsoever on the question of the existence of God or that they constitute grounds for impeaching the intellectual and/or moral quality of believers, today or in ages past.

Many people have been taken aback, and offended, by Hitchens' invective against Theresa of Calcutta, for instance. His language was tasteless in a vile way (that she was Albanian and extremely short -a "dwarf" in his expression- is just racist excrement with no bearing on the substance of the question). But, the core of his indictment of her is self-evidently true. This would have been obvious to a much wider public had he not chosen the despicable language that he used to express it.

He was also absolutely right in denying any kind of immunity to the Koran from the humanist and rationalist condemnation meted out against the pseudo-divine books of the other religions. Muslims, fundamentalists or moderates, in their own countries or in the West, are not entitled to any kind of deference on the part of free-thinking intellects (eastern or western) with respect to the absurdities comprised in their own "holy" fairy tale. We should be eternally grateful to Hitchens for trumpeting this very simple truth. This does not give license gratuitously to offend people's religious sensibilities, Christian or Muslim or Hebrew. It would, for instance be intolerable tyranny to force devout Muslims to imbibe alcohol or Jews to eat pork etc. -let alone to destroy their houses of worship or burn their books. But this is one thing, and another thing altogether to put a ban on criticism of the precepts enunciated in the Koran or the social norms prevalent in Muslim life (e.g. those pertaining to women) because those who believe in these things would be offended. This is totalitarian obscurantism -with murderous implications as was shown in the case of Hitchens' friend, the writer Salman Rushdie.

Hitchens was also right on the mark when he explained that Muslim fundamentalists (and I would add fundamentalists of all stripes, really) hate Western civilization not on account of the faults in it diagnosed by Western liberals and leftists. The hate the West on account of its positive and progressive traits, which Western liberals and leftists cherish and defend (or ought to, anyway), namely individual rights, the legal equality of the sexes, the freedom of conscience and speech and the separation of religion and the state. That is why the implicit and explicit ideological cover provided to Islamic fundamentalism by certain "anti-imperialist" elements in Western academia in particular is such a moral monstrosity. The glee with which these people and their flock greeted the destruction of the Twin Towers was an abomination that should never be forgotten. One half-excuses (but not quite) Hitchens for his ideological pirouettes post 9/11 if one understands them against such a background.

Having said all this, I must repeat that nothing that Hitchens, or his friend R. Dawkins, has said on the matter of God's existence per se, or on the status of religious faith in conscious life and the behavioral consequences from it has any value whatsoever. An atheist is just as likely as a theist to be moral or immoral, peaceful or violent, rational or irrational. Evil is not the exclusive preserve of the religious. Religion is not the central problem of our times. Politics is, including a politics stamped by a perverse construal of religiosity. Hitchens' carping mortally wounds the theologians, the ecclesiastical hierarchies and the theocrats of all religions. But it leaves unscathed those for whom religious feeling is an inner vocation and an existential commitment. To call these persons names (ignorant, anti-science, mindless, dupes etc.) just shows the paucity -precisely- of rational discourse that might somehow impinge upon their choices. It is mere bullying. Hitchens and Dawkins are not smarter than the sincere believer simply because they graduated from Oxbridge and they know their genetics. There is an insufferable kind of pompousness in this.

I may respect and need science, I may accept it as the truth about natural processes. But I may still find my existence immensely enriched by standing before Michelangelo's Sistine vision, and by living as if there were something behind it. Science cannot and may not outlaw poetic intuition. It has been the ambition of some hard-core scientism since the 17th century to do just that. It has not happened, simply because it cannot.

The cardinal value of the Enlightenment was tolerance of individual choice. The kind of crusading, hectoring Enlightenment that Hitchens and Dawkins represent at their worst is simply a self-defeating ideology, an extra infusion of hatred into the hate-filled cultural climate of our times.

Tuesday, December 6, 2011

Christian hubris, superbia, temeritas: on having to teach Augustine again

It was just the other day that I vented my anger at having to put up with Platonic rigmarole masquerading as "proof" of anything in particular. So it is only fitting that having taken it out on grandfather Plato that I should now turn to someone infinitely pettier and less arresting.

So here it is: why on earth do we still read or teach Augustine? His pseudo-explanation of the sack of Rome in 410 and of the the disintegration of the world of antiquity has exactly the same value as the explanation of AIDS as God's punishment for the degeneracy of the homosexuals -that is, exactly nil. Whereas his pretended unpacking of the various metaphysical conundrums regarding theodicy and the the liberum arbitrium amounts to nothing more than "God knows" and we do not deserve nor are we able to fathom his will. His entire thought can be summed up in one sentence: Christ is savior (I do not believe he would quarrel with this). Everything else is an interminable repetition of the exact same idea in different guises, i.e. a tediously belabored tautology. His notion that this unlocks all riddles of human existence is a very tall order for any normal individual. But maybe Augustine was not normal (for how can you characterize as moderately sane a person who believes that newborn infants deserve to burn in hell?).

So whence the ferocity of his religious passion? It is simply that for reasons that concern him personally, and are not in the least obligatory for anybody else, all other sources of meaning in his life dried up so he threw himself entirely into the Christian promise. He could no longer be fulfilled through love, friendship, service to the community or the life of reason or the imagination. So feeling that all these outlets of self-justification had been disgraced he cut himself off from ordinary humanity (and humaneness) and in a monstrous act of self-aggrandizement hitched himself to the wagon of Christ for a pretended soaring to heaven barred to the rest of us mortals. Augustine smiles maliciously as he wheezes past us and as he sees us shrink into imperceptibility in his glorious ascent. Why he felt betrayed by all the means of self-fulfillment that nature (and hence God, if you believe that God is the author of nature) places at human disposal is an interesting question. It may have to do with his own psychological peculiarities, or with the difficulties of an age out of joint or both. But it is certainly not of earth-shattering significance, i.e. a crisis of metaphysical dimensions that is revelatory of the deepest ontological essence of Being. That he may believe so is perhaps understandable, if not excusable. The we too ought to concur with this assessment of his is just laughable.

In the Christian intellectual tradition, if it be dignified by that name, we do not in general come across the slightest trace of the humility and the love that its representatives so pretentiously trumpet. In fact the opposite is the case. All we get is a venomous rant dripping with hatred and plain incomprehension of the traditions (especially the Hellenic tradition) they are are keen to damn.

But in Augustine the whole thing takes a particularly annoying turn (there is nothing more reprehensible in a thinker than being annoying).

For what we have here is egomania to the superlative degree, the boast by one individual that his "conversion" to the single and exclusive truth is at the same time paradigmatic of all conversions and declarative of the only truth there is on offer.

He may be an excellent writer of Latin prose: I cannot be the assessor of that. But this is not the palm he was claiming. Hence, we can judge him solely on the basis of what he himself considered his "accomplishments". And on all these the verdict can only be damning.

His legacy is, as we will see, threefold and on all counts deleterious. If we continue to refer to him it ought to be as an example to be avoided, as a kind of thinker that contaminated the European philosophical tradition with odious epistemological and moral stances. From these there flowed all the excesses and abuses both in thought and action that have marred the said tradition, i.e. intolerance, dogmatism, self-conceit, denying to others the very right to exist.
From this perspective all his affectation about "caritas" is just an empty show, just as it was in his great model, Paul. For Augustine does not love God, he loves his own God. And he does not love his neighbor, he loves only the neighbor that loves the same God as he. I do not need to point out all the neat uses that these precepts can be put to, if one is eager to disgrace and eliminate all those that think differently in reference to a canonic set of beliefs (religious, ethical, political, national or what have you).

The first governing thought in Augustine is that of the "illuminated" self. This is no other than his own self as illuminated by a light which that same self axiomatically defined as the divine one, brooking no objection on the matter. This is a closed epistemological circle, amounting to the simple idea that a thought that emerges in my mind is the truth simply because it emerges in my mind in a special way (accompanied by psychological fervor). And it is as vicious as it can get. Augustine impresses us by the emotional tumult in his soul, and by nothing more, for emotional urgency does not lend truth to a belief. All beliefs, true and false, morally right or wrong, can be accompanied by psychological intensity and sincerity. This does not in any way affect their epistemological or moral status.

Of course Augustine also has a text before him: scripture. But this text is asserted to be the truth, the whole truth and nothing but the truth, simply on account of Augustine's own conversion. The very same Augustine before the conversion declared that same scripture to be false.

So Just like Saul on the road to Damascus God entered the mind of Augustine, and from then on we are admonished to accept as truth what this particular illuminated individual declares to be such (including the Book). This continues to be no argument and no proof of whatever truth might or might not be found in the holy text. It is just an imposition, a threat, a cajolement, a flattery maybe to make yourself see something as true because Augustine so sees it and without subjecting it to any rational control. This is no wisdom, it is blindness. Faith is alright, and maybe unavoidable -even epistemologically speaking. But Paul's and Augustine's particular faith is alright and unavoidable for them and for them alone. It is not so for others who choose not to share it, who choose to pursue other faiths.

It is no surprise, therefore, that Augustine's newfound wisdom goes together with a rabid condemnation of reason (along with all other natural capacities and inclinations of the human person). His "teaching" amounts to a sustained shrillness, simply deafening you with the grandiloquence of his rhetoric and confounding you with the terror of his imaginings. And if you dare to raise your voice in inquiry concerning the meaning of scriptural pronouncements and the logical coherence of the whole system of "truths" therein, he will immediately cut you down with pitiless ferocity.

For the second guiding thought of his system is that Holy Writ is truth, but in numerous places this truth is "obscure". This means, mind you, not that it lacks meaning in itself, or that it is not well developed. It means that it is obscure to you, the reader, because your mind is weak and overwhelmed and deformed by sin, so that it cannot rise to the truth that is there in the holy word but humans cannot see it.

This is the purest of all pure sophisms. Under this maxim you can transform every nonsensical and/or criminal utterance or injunction into divine truth. If you do not understand the word of God (of the Church, of the Nation, of the Party) it is your fault because you are inherently deficient in spirit and intellectuality and morality for not having subjected yourself to the tutelage of those ontologically supreme entities. Worse still, if you proceed to claim that the obscurity of a given passage is due to the fact that it lacks sense, that it is a mere aggregation of sounds, then you are a convinced enemy of the truth and hence you do not deserve to exist. You are responsible for the obscurity just like you are responsible for all evil. God knows, even if no human does, and he is all-good even if his creation is replete with evil. Do not judge or question the hidden meanings and purposes of God.

What is understandable in scripture is so because God willed it, and what is incomprehensible is so also because God willed it. For He aimed to put human beings through the spiritual labor to eventually discover the hidden truth for themselves (here Augustine declares that he knows what are God's aims). And since ordinary humans will be incapable of so delving to the bottom of true insight, we will have permanent need of a body of illuminated saints and sages (such as Augustine) who will tutor us as to why the sundry stupidities of scripture, theology and ecclesiastical tradition are indeed utter wisdom and also chastise us if we resist this our moral and intellectual debasement. And if even after that there are still passages that cannot be penetrated, then that's that and nothing further can be said about it. God knows why he put them there. Probably to test our presumption to know all things. But if you say this, and Augustine is more than willing to say, you then again claim to know God's mind.

This entire doctrine of divine symbols and signs proceeding from a transcendent God to dumbfound mankind and empower an elite of authoritative and authoritarian guides is arguably the most detestable and the most destructive thought spun by the discombobulated brain of someone like Augustine (among many others) with a purpose of course to place himself in the seat of spiritual auctoritas. In this light the saint's conversion appears as what it truly is, namely as extreme and manic self-indulgence, as the madness of someone wishing to elevate his ego to the status of privileged receptacle of divinity.

Augustine's existential tribulations would be of interest if placed under a radically human sign, namely if presented as as paradigmatic of the haplessness of humanity in the midst of an inscrutable universe in which God is sorely missed and sought but it is doubtful whether he is ever found. For God is voiceless, and it is impossible to understand why he would privilege someone like Augustine to make privy to concerning the root mysteries of existence. But this is what Augustine assumes about himself. His torments are to be read not as human, but as paradigmatic of the way a human person was metamorphosed into a vessel of divinity. This is demanding too much of us poor sinners.

The claim might be somewhat credible if the said person's career subsequent to the supposed metamorphosis reeked of an aroma of meekness, understanding and humility, not least with regard to those resistant to his message: in this he would be truly imitating Jesus who sought the company of whores and tax collectors. But no.

All we get in Augustine is his fulminating denunciation of the lost world of pagan sinfulness, in other words of his own youth. There is not a scintilla of kindness in his utterings, just the imperiousness of someone convinced of having grabbed God by the beard (if not by the genitals) to turn him into his own private sponsor and protector.

Augustine hates himself, and who hates himself cannot love others. And it is this psychologically perverse relation of Augustine's to his pagan environment that brings us to the third governing assumption of his system. This one is also steeped in dishonesty for in it he is hell-bent in denying his own intellectual parents. In his egotistic theology Augustine remained a philosopher, i.e. someone determined to expound in quasi-rational terms the "true" solution to moral and intellectual problems deriving from his theological principles. He puts his mind to work in order to clarify some of the "obscurities" of Christian dogma (the presence of evil, the reality of freedom etc.), thus implicitly justifying the rationality that he has been despising all along. And in doing so he cannot but utilize the resources of Hellenic learning of his time. Augustine the philosopher (who denies being one) is a neo-Platonist as we all know, in that his solutions to the theological puzzles are purloined from that corpus: his illumination is the platonic methexis and/or emanation, his theory of evil is premised upon the principle of privation etc.

All that would be creditable, if he would acknowledge himself as a philosopher (with a theological bent to be sure). But he dissimulates: he abjures and calumniates philosophizing, denying in advance that it can achieve all those things that he himself obsessively employs it to achieve. This is not being straight and clear about what he is doing. What he has plagiarized from the stupendous intellectual labor of those he denounces he does not admit to but wants to claim as his own. In his advice in De doctrina christiana concerning the way the Christian needs to deal with pagan texts he concedes that there is a lot in Hellenic literature that is worth studying, especially moral precepts and a certain awareness of God (he means in the neoplatonic tradition primarily). But, he says, all the rest must be consigned to the fire. As to the above-mentioned premonitions of truth in pagan authors they are not the property of the pagans themselves: "they belong to us Christians". Somehow they must have stolen it from the antecedents of Christian wisdom ("Plato is Moses speaking Greek" was the preposterous canard of earlier Christian intellectuals) and so we are entitled to steal it back. This is deviousness, dishonesty, self-serving disingenuousness of the lowest kind.

This approach continues a long-practiced stratagem of the Alexandrian apologists and of the Cappadocians. But it is no less infuriating epistemologically and morally for having that illustrious pedigree. For whence Augustine's presumption to claim as his own by right the intellectual achievements of the Hellenes growing out of a glorious philosophical tradition having no truck with his "truths"? But, he retorts, they employed raw and unaided human reason, hence if they got something right they have no title to it. Christians on the contrary are led by the divinity and their works are the conduit of divine wisdom. Hellenic philosophy smacks of pride.

Well, it is is easy to decide who is full of intolerable and inexcusable pride here. There is no more shabby trick to declare a priori your own thoughts as connected to the divine source and hence true by definition. When Jesus was asked what is truth he remained silent. But our saint here goes one better on his Lord. One thing is striking about all these presumptuous and self-worshiping Christian theologians, namely that they have absolutely nothing to do with Jesus.

Hellenic reason may have failed in many things, but at least it never renounced its humanity. That is why it is still with us. Plato may have failed to scale the heights of divinity or the soul for all he claimed to have done, but he is one of us. We may chide him today, but we still revere him because he tried to take the human faculties as far as they could possibly go. There is a message there for today. Augustine's peregrinations are on the contrary futile and tedious for us. He had a problem with his carnality: so what? This sounds so petty now. Instead of dealing with it, instead of acknowledging that he is human, he thought that he could separate himself from his own substance and make the leap directly into the intelligible world. What self-infatuation, what pride!

Thursday, December 1, 2011

On "plaster", "bandaids" and "bazookas"

This is written in white-hot anger, after reading an article in the Handelsblatt. Economics is of course known as the dismal science, and most economically-minded people I know are indeed rather dismal fellows overall. But this mean-spiritedness cannot be accepted as a narcissistic affectation and a game of being wiser than thou (Besserwisserei) regardless of its consequences in the lives of real people and societies. But since the beginning of the crisis two years ago this is precisely the attitude of experts at every turn of events, no matter what the measures introduced by the political leaders or anybody else in Europe. If psychology is in the main what feeds the current downward spiral in the Eurozone, the goal of these wise analysts seems to have been all along to stoke the fires of despondency, systematically dismissing every new attempt at a solution as half-measures. In this way they incited the stampede of the herds in the marketplaces of the world that kept upturning the wagons of the politicians, only triumphantly to proclaim that, alas, the governments were driven by the markets and not the other way around. But this is what these commentators have convinced us that they wanted in the first place.

Yesterday all the major central banks of the globe undertook a series of concerted actions which at least signified a new determination to act decisively to reverse the rot. I cannot evaluate the economic reasoning behind these measures, but psychologically they provided a lift. They were immediately dismissed by all the commentators I read as window-dressing that leaves the core problems intact. Of course, in a sense, they are: for who in his/her right mind thinks at this stage that the core problems can be put away in one blow?!!! This churlishness, this niggardliness, this stinginess, this Schadenfreude is at best a puny little fart of a truism. A truism moreover that they will keep on applying no matter what comes next, on December 9 or any other date. If you do not give to any conceivable proposal the benefit of the doubt with respect to its future efficacy, then it will certainly fail because you are thus inculcating in the general psychology the a priori certainty that it will fail. But then the cause of the failure of the measure is not the ineptness of the measure itself, but rather your determination to bad-mouth it in advance no matter what. Yesterday's actions surely dealt with symptoms of the crisis. But these are critical symptoms, which if left unchecked will precipitate the universal collapse feared. But, oh!, the fact that they took those measures just shows how dire the situation has become, came the retort. So, in this reasoning, they should have done nothing in order not to appear to admit that the situation is desperate! This is so deep, it is way past my philosophy. What is wrong dealing with these symptoms, threatening a universal drying up of credit, first? This world coordination may just be a sign of a new policy beginning in the direction of tackling the core of the matter, which includes forcing Germany to abandon its bloody-mindedness about all sorts of things (as well as forcing Greece to abandon its habitual stupidity on just about everything). How can you exclude this possibility in advance? What lends to your insights such an implacable and indubitable grasp of the future. Extreme adversity is a persuasive teacher, and we may be facing the writing on the wall at this point, concerning the Euro and even the very existence of the European project in all its dimensions. Who can absolutely exclude that in these circumstances the various leaders will (under world pressure) abandon their petty bickering to commit themselves to something truly thoroughgoing? W. Muenchau says in the Financial Times that he is not certain that this law of extremity holds any longer in Europe and he gives just ten days to the Eurozone before it breaks apart. He may be right, but he might also turn out to be a Muenchausen on this one (I have the highest respect for this guy, don't misunderstand me). All I am trying to say is that I am sick and tired (and today positively incensed) after every turning point, great or small, to hear again that familiar carping drone of the experts, the same one from from yesterday and the day before, that "this does not go far enough", "this is merely plaster" etc. etc. If that is the depth of their analysis I am prepared to take up economics late in life for I can do it much better. Gloom-mongering is a secure line of business given the human condition.

There is another aspect to this compulsive nay-saying which is equally misguided. It is also premised on the notion that there are no longer in Europe political leaders "great" enough to rise to the occasion. This is to me plainly silly. Europe is the victim of its success, not its failure. The "great" leaders of the past made a mistake in opening the doors of the European house for all and sundry (including Greece) to enter, before the cement holding it together had solidified. But this was a "great" (meaning noble, great-hearted) mistake. It was also based on a plausible calculation that letting everyone in and forcing a common currency on most would in time blackmail them to adopt common ways of prudence as well as solidarity, besides inexorably pushing in the direction of a complete political union. This may have not been spelled out in so many words from the beginning, so there is indeed an element of dishonesty and deficient democratic legitimation here (as Issing and Sinn and Stark and Weber and other, open or hidden, foes of the Euro have consistently argued). On the other hand, no one can say that nobody suspected or even wished that to be the case. The Brits trumpeted it and stayed out, the Greeks for all their folly equally recognized and enthusiastically welcomed it in their official pronouncements. Well, the time for this radical turn has come. This is the crux of the matter. The decisions demanded are the most weighty possible, fraught with immensely complex consequences. So. what's the wonder that there is hesitation, dithering, backtracking etc.? When so many, great or mediocre no matter, have joined together collective deliberation is onerous and inefficient, but there is no other way -and it is the best way (this incidentally is straight out of Aristotle). When it was just between De Gaulle and Adenauer or even Kohl and Mitterand decisions could be reached in half a day. Today this is no longer possible irrespective of the caliber and worth of the participants. Hence, the complaint that there are no leaders in Europe today is a worthless side-show. The reason that the markets rush ahead of them is simply that this is what markets do in the pursuit of gain from a day to the next. If the politicians began to imitate the behavior of the markets, spasmodically reacting to any fancy or rumor that the economic press spread around in order to pacify the baby, their decisions would be of an immeasurably poorer quality. As it is, they have to balance the need for speed against the need for substance and seriousness -with a view to a political and a cultural future that the markets do not give a fart about. In this contest they may lose out, but if they are to succeed this is the way. And in this I, for whatever it is worth, am an optimist. If even the Greek political class were forced to abandon some of their destructive habits (and there is no more obstinate beast around), then European leaders will eventually find the way, and the glow of the vision will be restored. For nothing succeeds like success, and the markets know that better than anyone.